Home On Pascal's Wager
Post
Cancel

On Pascal's Wager

I wanted to post the text of Pascal’s wager here for reference. I can’t depend on other sources to stay where I might point you, so I’m adding it here so I can self-link. So, please enjoy the full text of the essay without quotes or other pesky editorializing punctuation.

Pascal’s Wager, by Blaise Pascal

Infinity. Nothingness. Our soul has been cast into the body, where it finds number, time and dimension. It reasons thereupon, and calls it nature, necessity, and can believe nothing else.
Unity added to infinity adds nothing to it, any more than does one foot added to infinite length. The finite is annihilated in presence of the infinite, and becomes pure nothingness. So does our mind before God; so does our justice before divine justice. There is not so great a disproportion between human and divine justice as between unity and infinity.
The justice of God must be as vast as His mercy. But his justice done upon the reprobate is not so vast as, and should shock us less than, His mercy shown towards the elect.
We know that the infinite exists, but we are ignorant of its nature. Since we know it is false to say that number is finite, it must be true that there is infinity in number. But we do not know what it is. We cannot say that it is even, or that it is odd. Yet it is a number, and every number is either even or odd (this is certainly true of every finite number). So we may perfectly well know that God exists, without knowing what He is.
Is there not one substantial truth, seeing that there are so many things which are not truth itself?
We know then the existence and nature of the finite, because we too are finite and have extension. We know the existence of the infinite, but not its nature; for, like us, it has extension but no limits such as we have. But we know neither the existence nor the nature of God, because He has neither extension or limits. But by faith we know His existence; in the light of glory we shall know His nature. I have already shown that there is nothing to prevent our knowing the existence of a thing, without knowing its nature.
Let us speak now according to natural lights.
If there is a God, He is infinitely incomprehensible, since, having neither parts nor limits, He has no affinity with us. We are incapable, therefore, of knowing either what He is or if He is. That being so, who will dare undertake to decide this question? Not we, who have no affinity with Him.
Who then can blame the Christians for not being able to give reasons for their belief, professing as they do a religion which they cannot explain by reason. They declare, when expounding to the world, that it is foolishness, stultitiam;1 and then you complain that they do not prove it! If they proved it they would give the lie to their own worlds; it is in lacking proofs that they do not lack sense.
‘Yes, but while this is an excuse for those who offer it as such, and frees them from blame for not basing their beliefs upon reason, it does not excuse those who accept what they say.’
Let us examine this point of view and declare: ‘Either God exists, or He does not.’ To which view shall we incline? Reason cannot decide for us one way or the other: we are separated by an infinite gulf. At the extremity of this infinite distance a game is in progress, where either heads or tails may turn up. What will you wager? According to reason you cannot bet either way; according to reason you can defend neither proposition.
So do not attribute error to those who have made a choice; for you know nothing about it.
‘No; I will not blame them for having made this choice, but for having made one at all; for since he who calls heads and he who calls tails are equally at fault, both are in the wrong. The right thing is not to wager at all.’ Yes; but a bet must be laid. There is no option: you have joined the game. Which will you choose, then? Since a choice has to be made, let us see which is of least moment to you. You have two things to lose, the true and the good; and two things to wager, your reason and your will, your knowledge and your happiness; and your nature has two things to shun, error and unhappiness. Your reason suffers no more violence in choosing one rather than another, since you must of necessity make a choice. That is one point cleared up. But what about your happiness? Let us weigh the gain and the loss involved in wagering that God exists. Let us estimate these two probabilities; it you win, you win all; if you lose, you lose nothing. Wager then, without hesitation, that He does exist.
‘That is all very fine. Yes, I must wager, but maybe I am wagering too much.’
Let us see. Since there is an equal risk of winning and of losing, if you had only two lives to win you might still wager; but if there were three lives to win, you would still have to play (since you are under the necessity of playing); and being thus obliged to play, you would be imprudent not to risk your life to win three in a game where there is an equal chance of winning and losing. But there is an eternity of life and happiness. That being so, if there were an infinity of chances of which only one was in your favour, you would still do right to stake one to win two, and you would act unwisely in refusing to play one life against three, in a game where you had only one chance out of an infinite number, if there were an infinity of an infinitely happy life to win. But here there is an infinity of infinitely happy life to win, one chance of winning against a finite number of chances of losing, and what you stake is finite. That removes all doubt as to choice; wherever the infinite is, and there is not an infinity of chances of loss against the chance of winning, there are no two ways about it, all must be given. And so, when a man is obliged to play, he must renounce reason to preserve his life, rather than risk it for infinite gain which is just as likely to occur as loss of nothing.
For it is no use alleging the uncertainty of winning and the certainty of risk, or to say that the infinite distance between the certainty of what one risks and the uncertainty of what one will win equals that between the finite good, which one certainly risks, and the infinite, which is uncertain. That is not so; every player risks a certainty to win an uncertainty, and yet he risks a finite certainty to win a finite uncertainty, without offending reason. There is no infinite distance between the certainty risked and the uncertainty of the gain; it is not true. There is, indeed, infinity between the certainty of winning and the certainty of losing, but the uncertainty of winning is proportionate to the certainty of what is risked, according to the proportion of the chances of gain and loss. Hence, if there are many risks on one side as on the other, the right course is to play even; and then the certainty of the risk is equal to the uncertainty of the gain, so far are they from being infinitely distant. Thus our proposition is of infinite force, when there is the infinite at stake in a game where there are equal chances of winning and losing, but the infinite to gain. This is conclusive, and if men are capable of truth at all, there it is.
‘I agree, I admit it; but is there no way of getting a look behind the scenes?’ Yes, Scripture and the rest, etc. ‘Quite; but my hand are tied and my mouth is gagged; I am forced to wager, and am not free; no one frees me from these bonds, and I am so made that I cannot believe. What then do you wish me to do?
That is true. But understand at least that your ability to believe is the result of your passions; for, although reason inclines you to believe, you cannot do so. Try therefore to convince yourself, not by piling up proofs of God, but by subduing your passions. You desire to attain faith, but do not know the way. You would like to cure yourself of unbelief, and you ask for remedies. Learn of those who were bound and gagged like you, and who now stake all they possess. They are men who know the road you desire to follow, and who have been cured of a sickness of which you desire to be cured. Follow the way by which they set out, acting as if they already believed, taking holy water, having masses said, etc. Even this will naturally cause you to believe and bunt your cleverness. ‘But that is what I fear.’ Why? What have you to lose?
But to show that such practices lead you to belief, it is those things which will curtail your passions which are your main obstacles. End of this discourse. Now, to what harm will you come by making this choice? You will be faithful, honest, humble, grateful, generous, a sincere friend, truthful. Certainly you will not enjoy these pernicious delights—glory and luxury; but will you not experience others?
I tell you, you will thereby profit in this life; and at every step you take along this road you will see so great an assurance of gain, and so little in what you risk, that you will come to recognize your stake to have been laid for something certain, infinite, which has cost you nothing.
‘Oh, your discourse delights me, carries me away!’
If it pleases you and appears convincing, know it has been uttered by a man who has knelt, both before and after its delivery, in prayer to that Being, infinite and without parts, before whom he submits all that is his, begging Him to subject to Himself all that is yours, for your own good and for His glory; and thus strength is made consistent with lowliness.

A Criticism of the Wager

Pascal is assuming a Christian1 view on God. He is relying on the convincing power of the Bible (testaments old and new) to defend its own assertions and/or leaving the debate about the Bible’s historical accuracy for another forum.

Critics who bring this up aren’t really serious people, in my opinion. It’s the equivalent of saying, “If his premise is wrong, then he’s wrong.” This is not really a conversation-advancing criticism. To put it into a logical perspective it’s like Pascal is saying:

P → Q. If(P) it’s possible for a benevolent God to exist, then(Q) it’s in your best interest to act as though he does and try to follow his commandments.

Then his critics are saying, yeah, but what if it’s really:

!P → !Q. If(!P) a benevolent god doesn’t exist, then it’s not(!Q) beneficial for you to act as though he does and follow his commandments.

To put it in more practical terms, it’s as if Pascal is standing on a wall and inviting others to come up and see the view, but instead of taking him at his word and accepting the invitation, they instead say, “Yeah, but if the wall weren’t there, you wouldn’t have the view.” It’s not enough for them to simply assert that Pascal’s premise is flawed and then make arguments based on that assertion. A more convincing criticism would involve the construction of their own wall which requires too much effort for most.

Additionally this is a logical fallacy known as denying the antecedent, and it becomes really obvious when you replace the arguments.

Denying the Antecedent: a fallacy in formal logic where in a standard if/then premise, the antecedent (what comes after the “if”) is made not true, then it is concluded that the consequent (what comes after the “then”) is not true2

P → Q If someone opens the fire-hydrant, then it will be wet on the street.
!P → !Q If someone does not open the fire-hydrant then it will not be wet on the street.

Do you see how that doesn’t follow? It’s not a logical descendant of the arguer’s premise and it’s not necessarily true either. Rain, for example, can also moisten the street.

Dan’s Takeaways

What I believe he is trying to say

When I read Pascal’s wager, I get the sense that he was trying to instill a sense of urgency into his readers to examine their assumptions. Pascal does a better job than I think I could ever do to illustrate that you have to make a choice. You have but one life to live and you have to choose in each moment which assumption your behavior serves. Pascal is pointing out that if you assume God does not exist, your behavior will necessarily reflect that assumption, and you are making a bet with your life about that. If you decide to assume that God does exist, the same will be true. You are making a choice which will reflect in your behavior about what you believe.

What’s interesting about Pascal’s wager is the way he frames what you stand to gain or to lose based on your wager.

 God does existGod does not exist
Belief Behaviorinfinite gainfinite loss
Non-belief behaviorinfinite lossfinite loss

When you lay the arguments out like this, it seems pretty obvious that it’s the most rational decision to behave as though he exists because you stand to gain something infinitely good if he’s right and you’re only risking something finite if he’s wrong.

He is illustrating that even if you “subdue your passions” you are really sacrificing very little. If you look at what you’re actually giving up, it all has to do with just controlling your body and trying to serve other people. The wager is actually very small compared to what you’re hoping to get.

What Dan would add

I accept most of Pascal’s assumptions, but there are some that I take issue with:

Certainly you will not enjoy these pernicious delights—glory and luxury;

I believe, and have see in my own life, that keeping the commandments does not lead to loss; or, more precisely, it does not lead to the loss of anything I want to keep. What has lead to loss for me has not been my decision to try to keep the commandments. Instead, it has been my own bad decision-making, or the choices of others. I would also argue that there is a certain amount of chaos that exists regardless of consistently good decision-making or commandment-keeping. What I do lose as a direct result of commandment-keeping is hopelessness and confusion.

I would also encourage Pascal to add, were I his brother or his friend, that accepting the wager yields immediate results. The injection of hope and joy into my life as a result of a belief in a benevolent higher power is a constant source of strength for me and I think it sweetens the pot. While I still believe that there is an infinite reward in the end, I believe that risking those chips begins to pay off just as soon as you place them on the table, and I have had the privilege of experiencing many delights and luxuries in the midst of my belief-based behavior.

Footnotes

  1. “Christian” is a loaded term. In this context, I’m taking the dictionary definition 

  2. Logically Fallacious 

This post is licensed under CC BY 4.0 by the author.